Brevity can mean a brief passage
By Prof Dr
Sohail Ansari “It was narrated that Abu Hanifa said to Dawud al-Taa’i, “Why do you prefer seclusion?” Dawud replied, “To struggle against
myself to leave disputing.” Abu Hanifah said, “Attend meetings, listen to what
is said, and remain silent.” Dawud said, “I have done so, but I have found
nothing heavier than this.”
Long passage can be succinct
· Conciseness is
not expressing in a few words rather it is not exceeding the words required for
expression.
The Ethics of Leadership
The Prophet (pbuh) and his close companions all maintained
strong moral ethics while in positions of authority. Omar, the second caliph,
has particularly left a legacy of leadership which modern leaders can learn
much from. Upon assuming the role of Caliph, he said: “In the performance of my
duties, I will seek guidance from the Holy Book, and will follow the examples
set by the Holy Prophet and Abu Bakr [the first Caliph]. In this task, I seek
your assistance. If I follow the right path, follow me. If I deviate from the
right path, correct me so that we are not led astray.”
Addressing the needs and concerns of the people was no doubt
paramount in his reign and under the rule of other close companions of the
Prophet (pbuh). In fact, Omar was even keen on safeguarding the well-being of
animals, he would say, “If a mule stumbled in Iraq, I would be afraid that
Allah [God] would ask me, why did you not pave the road for it Omar?”
As illustrated in A
History of Muslim Civilization by
Abiva and Durkee, Omar “expected his leaders to live up to ethical standards.”
The list below shows some of the criteria a leader should have according to
Omar.
1. No nepotism or hereditary
succession.
2. The people should be able to
reach the leader easily to voice any of their concerns or suggestions.
3. The ruler should seek counsel,
accept criticism, and be willing to rectify his mistakes.
4. The army exists to protect the
people of the nation, not protect the leader from the people.
The above examples of Prophet Muhammad (pbuh) and Omar give us
priceless models in governance. Not only was shura and consultation key in their rule,
they also upheld high morals and ethics. Every living entity was given
importance, be it animal or human, which created an empowered society where the
rights of its subjects were paramount and people were given the opportunity to
thrive. These standards are especially relevant for our world today in our
quest for democracy.
Communication studies is an academic discipline that
deals with processes of human communication. There are three types of
communication: verbal, involving listening to a person to understand the meaning
of a message; written, in which a message is read; and nonverbal communication involving observing a person and
inferring meaning.[1] The discipline encompasses a range of topics,
from face-to-face conversation to mass media outlets such as television
broadcasting. Communication studies also examines how messages are interpreted
through the political, cultural, economic, semiotic, hermeneutic, and social
dimensions of their contexts.
Presupposition
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
In the branch of linguistics known as pragmatics, a presupposition (or PSP)
is an implicit assumption about the world or background belief relating to an
utterance whose truth is taken for granted in discourse. Examples of presuppositions include:
·
Jane no
longer writes fiction.
·
Presupposition:
Jane once wrote fiction.
·
Have you
stopped eating meat?
·
Presupposition:
you had once eaten meat.
·
Have you
talked to Hans?
·
Presupposition:
Hans exists.
A presupposition must
be mutually known or assumed by the speaker and addressee for the utterance to
be considered appropriate in context. It will generally remain a necessary
assumption whether the utterance is placed in the form of an assertion, denial,
or question, and can be associated with a specific lexical item or grammatical
feature (presupposition trigger) in the utterance.
Crucially, negation of
an expression does not change its presuppositions: I want to do it again and I
don't want to do it again both
presuppose that the subject has done it already one or more times; My wife is pregnant and My
wife is not pregnant both
presuppose that the subject has a wife. In this respect, presupposition is distinguished
from entailment and implicature. For example, The president was assassinated entails that The president is dead, but if
the expression is negated, the entailment is not necessarily true.
Negation of a sentence containing a
presupposition[edit]
If presuppositions of a sentence are not consistent with the
actual state of affairs, then one of two approaches can be taken. Given the
sentences My wife is pregnant and My
wife is not pregnant when one
has no wife, then either:
1.
Both the sentence and its negation are false; or
2.
Strawson's approach: Both "my wife is
pregnant" and "my wife is not pregnant" use a wrong
presupposition (i.e. that there exists a referent which
can be described with the noun phrase my
wife) and therefore can not be assigned truth values.
Bertrand Russell tries to solve this dilemma with two
interpretations of the negated sentence:
1.
"There exists exactly one person, who is my wife and who is
not pregnant"
2.
"There does not exist exactly one person, who is my wife
and who is pregnant."
For the first phrase, Russell would claim that it is false,
whereas the second would be true according to him.
Projection of presuppositions[edit]
A presupposition of a part of an utterance is sometimes also a
presupposition of the whole utterance, and sometimes not. For instance, the
phrase my wife triggers the presupposition that I
have a wife. The first sentence below carries that presupposition, even though
the phrase occurs inside an embedded clause. In the second sentence, however,
it does not. John might be mistaken about his belief that I have a wife, or he
might be deliberately trying to misinform his audience, and this has an effect
on the meaning of the second sentence, but, perhaps surprisingly, not on the
first one.
1.
John thinks that my
wife is beautiful.
2.
John said that my
wife is beautiful.
Thus, this seems to be a property of the main verbs of the
sentences, think and say,
respectively. After work by Lauri Karttunen,[1] verbs
that allow presuppositions to "pass up" to the whole sentence
("project") are called holes,
and verbs that block such passing up, or projection of presuppositions are called plugs. Some linguistic
environments are intermediate between plugs and holes: They block some
presuppositions and allow others to project. These are called filters. An example of such an
environment are indicative
conditionals ("If-then"
clauses). A conditional sentence contains an antecedent and a consequent. The antecedent is
the part preceded by the word "if," and the consequent is the part
that is (or could be) preceded by "then." If the consequent contains
a presupposition trigger, and the triggered presupposition is explicitly stated
in the antecedent of the conditional, then the presupposition is blocked.
Otherwise, it is allowed to project up to the entire conditional. Here is an
example:
If I have a wife, then my wife is blonde.
Here, the presupposition triggered by the expression my wife (that I have a wife) is blocked,
because it is stated in the antecedent of the conditional: That sentence
doesn't imply that I have a wife. In the following example, it is not stated in
the antecedent, so it is allowed to project, i.e. the sentence does imply that I have a wife.
If it's already 4am, then my wife is probably angry.
Hence, conditional sentences act as filters for presuppositions that are triggered
by expressions in their consequent.
A significant amount of current work in semantics and pragmatics is
devoted to a proper understanding of when and how presuppositions project.
Presupposition triggers[edit]
A presupposition trigger is a lexical item or linguistic
construction which is responsible for the presupposition.[2] The
following is a selection of presuppositional triggers following Stephen C. Levinson's
classic textbook on Pragmatics,
which in turn draws on a list produced by Lauri Karttunen. As is customary, the
presuppositional triggers themselves are italicized, and the symbol »
stands for 'presupposes'.[3]
Definite descriptions[edit]
Main article: Definite description
Definite descriptions are phrases of the form "the X"
where X is a noun phrase. The description is said to be proper when the phrase applies to exactly one
object, and conversely, it is said to be improper when either there exist more than one
potential referents, as in "the senator from Ohio", or none at all,
as in "the king of France". In conventional speech, definite descriptions
are implicitly assumed to be proper, hence such phrases trigger the
presupposition that the referent is unique and existent.
·
John saw the
man with two heads.
»there exists a man with two heads.
»there exists a man with two heads.
Factive verbs[edit]
See also: Epistemology § Truth
In Western epistemology, there is a tradition originating with Plato of defining knowledge as justified
true belief. On this definition, for someone to know X, it is required that X
be true. A linguistic question thus arises regarding the usage of such phrases:
does a person who states "John knows X" implicitly claim the truth of
X? Steven Pinker explored this question in a popular science format in a 2007 book on language and
cognition, using a widely publicized example from a speech by a U.S. president.[4] A
2003 speech by George W. Bush included the line, "British Intelligence has
learned that Saddam Hussein recently sought significant quantities of uranium
from Africa."[5] Over
the next few years, it became apparent that this intelligence lead was
incorrect. But the way the speech was phrased, using a factive verb, implicitly
framed the lead as truth rather than hypothesis. The factivity thesis, the
proposition that relational predicates having to do with knowledge, such as knows, learn, remembers, and realized,
presuppose the factual truth of their object, however, was subject to notable
criticism by Allan Hazlett.[6]
·
Martha regrets drinking John's home brew.
·
Presupposition: Martha did in fact drink John's home brew.
·
Frankenstein was aware that Dracula was there.
·
Presupposition: Dracula was in fact there.
·
John realized that he was in debt.
·
Presupposition: John was in fact in debt.
·
It was odd how proud he was.
·
Presupposition: He was in fact proud.
Some further factive predicates: know; be sorry that; be proud that;
be indifferent that; be glad that; be sad that.
Implicative verbs[edit]
·
John managed to open the door.
»John tried to open the door.
»John tried to open the door.
·
John forgot to lock the door.
»John ought to have locked, or intended to lock, the door.
»John ought to have locked, or intended to lock, the door.
Some further implicative predicates: X happened to V»X didn't plan
or intend to V; X avoided Ving»X was expected
to, or usually did, or ought to V,
etc.
Change of state verbs[edit]
·
John stopped teasing his wife.
»John had been teasing his wife.
»John had been teasing his wife.
·
Joan began teasing her husband.
»Joan hadn't been teasing her husband.
»Joan hadn't been teasing her husband.
·
The flying saucer came again.
»The flying saucer came before.
»The flying saucer came before.
·
You can't get gobstoppers anymore.
»You once could get gobstoppers.
»You once could get gobstoppers.
·
Carter returned to power.
»Carter held power before.
»Carter held power before.
Further iteratives: another
time; to come back; restore; repeat; for the nth time.
Temporal clauses[edit]
·
Before Strawson was even born, Frege noticed
presuppositions.
»Strawson was born.
»Strawson was born.
·
While Chomsky was revolutionizing linguistics,
the rest of social science was asleep.
»Chomsky was revolutionizing linguistics.
»Chomsky was revolutionizing linguistics.
·
Since Churchill died, we've lacked a leader.
»Churchill died.
»Churchill died.
Further temporal clause constructors: after; during; whenever; as (as in As John was getting up, he slipped).
Cleft sentences[edit]
·
Cleft construction: It was Henry that kissed Rosie.
»Someone kissed Rosie.
»Someone kissed Rosie.
·
Pseudo-cleft construction: What John lost was his wallet.
»John lost something.
»John lost something.
Comparisons and contrasts[edit]
Comparisons and contrasts may be marked by stress (or by other
prosodic means), by particles like "too", or by comparatives
constructions.
·
Marianne called Adolph a male chauvinist, and then HE insulted HER.
»For Marianne to call Adolph a male chauvinist would be to insult him.
»For Marianne to call Adolph a male chauvinist would be to insult him.
·
Carol is a
better linguist than Barbara.
»Barbara is a linguist.
»Barbara is a linguist.
Counterfactual conditionals[edit]
·
If the notice had only said 'mine-field' in Welsh as well as in
English, we would never have lost poor Llewellyn.
»The notice didn't say 'mine-field' in Welsh.
»The notice didn't say 'mine-field' in Welsh.
Questions[edit]
Presuppose a seeking for what is sought.
Possessive case[edit]
·
John's children
are very noisy.
»John has children.
»John has children.
Accommodation of
presuppositions[edit]
A presupposition of a sentence must normally be part of the common ground of the utterance context (the shared
knowledge of the interlocutors)
in order for the sentence to be felicitous. Sometimes, however, sentences may
carry presuppositions that are not part of the common ground and nevertheless
be felicitous. For example, I can, upon being introduced to someone, out of the blue explain that my wife is a dentist, this without my addressee having ever
heard, or having any reason to believe that I have a wife. In order to be able
to interpret my utterance, the addressee must assume that I have a wife. This
process of an addressee assuming that a presupposition is true, even in the
absence of explicit information that it is, is usually called presupposition accommodation.
We have just seen that presupposition triggers like my wife (definite descriptions)
allow for such accommodation. In "Presupposition and Anaphora: Remarks on
the Formulation of the Projection Problem",[7] the
philosopher Saul Kripke noted
that some presupposition triggers do not seem to permit such accommodation. An
example of that is the presupposition trigger too.
This word triggers the presupposition that, roughly, something parallel to what
is stated has happened. For example, if pronounced with emphasis on John, the following sentence
triggers the presupposition that somebody other than John had dinner in New York
last night.
John had dinner in New
York last night, too.
But that presupposition, as stated, is completely trivial, given
what we know about New York. Several million people had dinner in New York last
night, and that in itself doesn't satisfy the presupposition of the sentence.
What is needed for the sentence to be felicitous is really that somebody
relevant to the interlocutors had dinner in New York last night, and that this
has been mentioned in the previous discourse, or that this information can be
recovered from it. Presupposition triggers that disallow accommodation are
called anaphoric presupposition triggers.
Presupposition in critical discourse analysis[edit]
Critical
discourse analysis (CDA)
seeks to identify presuppositions of an ideological nature. CDA is critical,
not only in the sense of being analytical, but also in the ideological sense.[8] Van Dijk (2003)
says CDA "primarily studies the way social power abuse, dominance, and
inequality" operate in speech acts (including
written text)—"text and talk".[8] Van
Dijk describes CDA as written from a particular point of view:[8] "dissendent
research" aimed to "expose" and "resist social inequality."[8] One
notable feature of ideological presuppositions researched in CDA is a concept
termed synthetic
personalisation.[citation
needed]
Context (language use)
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
In semiotics, linguistics, sociology and anthropology, context refers to those objects or entities
which surround a focal event,
in these disciplines typically a communicative event, of some kind. Context is
"a frame that surrounds the event and provides resources for its
appropriate interpretation."[1]:2-3 It is thus a relativistic concept,
only definable with respect to some focal event, not independently.
In linguistics[edit]
Verbal context refers
to the text or speech surrounding an expression (word, sentence, or speech act).
Verbal context influences the way an expression is understood; hence the norm
of not citing people out of context. Since much contemporary linguistics takes
texts, discourses, or conversations as the object of analysis, the modern study
of verbal context takes place in terms of the analysis of discourse structures
and their mutual relationships, for instance the coherence relation between sentences.
Traditionally, in sociolinguistics, social contexts were defined in terms of objective
social variables, such as those of class, gender, age or race. More recently,
social contexts tend to be defined in terms of the social identity being
construed and displayed in text and talk by language users. Influenced by
space.
The influence of context parameters on language use or discourse
is usually studied in terms of language
variation, style or register (see Stylistics). The basic assumption here is
that language users adapt the properties of their language use (such as
intonation, lexical choice, syntax, and other aspects of formulation) to the current
communicative situation. In this sense, language use or discourse may be called
more or less 'appropriate' in a given context. It is the language or derigitave
terms surrounding set paragraph, novel or article.
In linguistic anthropology[edit]
In the theory of sign phenomena, adapted from that of Charles Sanders Peirce,
which forms the basis for much contemporary work in linguistic anthropology, the concept of
context is integral to the definition of the index,
one of the three classes of signs comprising Peirce's second trichotomy. An
index is a sign which signifies by virtue of "pointing to" some
component in its context, or in other words an indexical sign is related to its
object by virtue of their co-occurence within some kind of contextual frame.[2]
Contextual variables[edit]
Communicative systems presuppose contexts that are structured in
terms of particular physical and communicative dimensions, for instance time,
location, and communicative role.
Comments
Post a Comment