Academic Research By Prof Dr Sohail Ansari & A PARADIGM OF PHILOSOPHY
"Contemplating deeply for one hour (with sincerity) is
better than 70 years of (mechanical) worship."
·
Research is only
academic if its implications do not go beyond the thesis itself.
“As for the future, your task is not to foresee it, but to enable
it.” ---Antoine de
Saint-Exupery
JANICE MOULTON A PARADIGM OF
PHILOSOPHY: THE ADVERSARY METHOD THE UNHAPPY CONFLATION OF AGGRESSION WITH
SUCCESS
It is frequently thought
that there are attributes, or kinds of behavior, that it is good for one sex
to have and bad for the other sex to have. Aggression is a particularly interesting example of
such an attribute. This paper investigates and criticizes a model of philosophic methodology
that accepts a positive view of aggressive behavior and uses it as a paradigm of philosophic
reasoning. But before I turn to this paradigm, I want to challenge the broader
view of aggression that permits it positive connotations. Defined as “an
offensive action or procedure, especially a
culpable unprovoked overt hostile attack,”
aggression normally has well deserved negative connotations. Perhaps a standard
image of aggression is that of an animal in the wild trying to take over some
other animal’s territory or attacking it to eat it. In human contexts,
aggression often invokes anger, uncontrolled range, and belligerence. However,
this negative concept, when it is specifically connected to males qua males or to workers in
certain professions (sales, management, law, philosophy, politics) often takes
on positive associations. In a civilized society, physical aggression is likely
to land one in a jail or a mental institution. But males and workers in certain
professions are not required to physically attack or eat their customers and
coworkers to be considered aggressive. In these contexts, aggression is thought
to be related to more positive concepts such as power, activity, ambition,
authority, competence, and effectiveness – concepts that are related to success
in these professions. And exhibition of these positive concepts is considered
evidence that one is, or has been, aggressive. Aggression may have no causal
bearing on competence, superiority, power, etc., but if many people believe
aggressive behavior is a sign of these properties, then one may have to learn
to behave aggressively in order to appear competent, to seem superior, and to
gain or maintain power. This poses a dilemma for anyone who wants to have those
positive qualities, but does not wish to engage in “culpable unprovoked overt hostile attacks.” Of reluctant aggressors, males have an advantage over females
members of the masculine gender, their aggression is thought to be “natural.”
Even if they do not engage in aggressive behavior, they can still be perceived
as possessing that trait, inherently, as a disposition. And if they do behave
aggressively, their behavior can be excused – after all, it’s natural. Since
women are not perceived as being dispositionally aggressive, it looks like they
would have to behave aggressively in order to be thought aggressive. On the
other hand, since women are not expected to be aggressive, we are much more
likely to notice the slightest aggressive behavior on the part of a woman while
ignoring more blatant examples by men just because they are not thought
unusual. But when done by a female, it may be considered all the more
unpleasant because it seems unnatural. Alternatively, it may be that a woman
who exhibits competence, energy, ambition, etc. may be thought aggressive and
therefore unnatural even without behaving aggressively. Since, as I shall
argue, aggressive behavior is unlikely to win friends and influence people in
the way that one would like, this presents a special problem for women. Some
feminists dismiss the sex distinction that views aggression in a female as a
negative quality and then encourage females to behave aggressively in order to
further their careers. I am going to, instead, question
the assumption that aggression deserves association with more positive
qualities. I think it is a mistake
to suppose that an aggressive person is more likely to be energetic, effective,
competent, powerful or successful and also a mistake to suppose that an
energetic, effective, etc. person is therefore aggressive. Even those who object to sex-roles stereotyping seldom balk specifically at the
assumption that more aggressive people are better suited to “be the
breadwinners and play the active role in the production of commodities of
society”, but only at the assumption that aggression is more natural to one sex
than the other.
1 Robin Lakoff assumes that
more aggressive speech is both more effective and typical of males, and objects
to the socialization that forbids direct questions and assertions, devoid of
polite phrases, in women’s speech.
2 Lakoff recognizes that
the speech she characterizes as women’s speech is frequently used by male
academics, but she still assumes that aggressive speech is more powerful and
more effective. She does not see that polite, nonabrupt speech, full of hesitations and qualifiers
can be a sign of great power and very effective in giving the impression of
great thought and deliberation, or in getting one’s listeners on one’s side.
Although polite, nonabrupt speech can be more effective and have more power
than aggressive speech, the conceptual
conflation of aggression with positive concepts has made this hard to remember.
THE
ADVERSARY METHOD
Consider some professional
occasions where aggression might be thought an asset. Aggression is often
equated with energy, but one can be energetic and work hard without being
hostile. It may seem that aggression is essential where there is competition,
but people who just try to do their best, without
deliberately trying to do in the other guy
may do equally well or even better. Feelings of hostility may be distracting,
and a goal of defeating another may sidetrack one to the advantage of a third
party. Even those who think it is a dog-eat-dog world can see that there is a
difference between acting to defeat or undermine competition and acting
aggressively towards that competition. Especially if one’s success depends on
other parties, it is likely to be far wiser to appear friendly than to engage
in aggressive behavior. And in professions where mobility is a sign of success,
today’s competitors may be tomorrow’s colleagues. So if aggression is likely to
make enemies, as it seems designed to do, it is a bad strategy in these
professions. What about other professional activities? A friendly, warm,
nonadversarial manner surely does not interfere with persuading customers to
buy, getting employees to carry out directions conscientiously, convincing
juries, teaching students, getting help and cooperation from coworkers, and
promotions from the boss. An aggressive manner is more likely to be a hindrance
in these activities. If these considerations make us more able to distinguish
aggression from professional competence, then they will have served as a useful
introduction to the main object of this essay: an
inquiry into a paradigm of philosophy that, perhaps tricked by the conflation
of aggression and competence, incorporates aggression into its methodology.
SCIENTIFIC REASONING Once upon a time it was thought that scientific claims were, or
ought to be, objective and value-free; that expressions of value were distinguishable from expressions
of fact, and that science ought to confine itself to the latter. This view was
forsaken, reluctantly by some, when it was recognized that theories incorporate values, because they advocate
one way of describing the world over others, and that even observations
of facts are made from some viewpoint or theory about the world already
presupposed.
3 Still devoted to a fact-value distinction,
Popper recognized that scientific statements invoked values, but believed that
the reasoning in science was objective and value-free.
4 Popper argued that the
primary reasoning in science is deductive.Theories in science propose laws of
the form “All A’s are B’s” and the job of scientific research is to find, or set up,
instances of 152 JANICE MOULTON A and see if they fail to produce or correlate
with instances of B. The
test of a theory was that it could withstand attempts to falsify it. A good theory encouraged such
attempts by making unexpected and broad claims rather than narrow and expected
claims. If instances of B failed to occur given instances of A, then the theory
was falsified. A new theory that could account for the failure of B to occur in
the same deductive manner would replace the old theory.
The reasoning used to discover theories, the way a theory related to physical
or mathematical models or other beliefs, was not
considered essential to the scientific
enterprise. On this view, only the thinking that was exact and certain,
objective and value-free was essential to science. However, Kuhn then argued that even the
reasoning used in science is not value free or certain.
Science involves more than
a set of independent generalizations about the world waiting to be falsified by
a single counterinstance. It involves a system, or “paradigm,” of not only
generalizations and concepts, but beliefs about the methodology and evaluation
of research: about what are good questions to ask, what are proper developments
of the theory, what are acceptable research methods. One theory replaces
another, not because it functions successfully as a major premise in a greater
number of deductions, but because it answers some questions that the other theory does not – even though it may not answer some questions the other theory
does. Theory changes occur because one theory is more satsifying than the
other, because the questions it answers are considered more important. Research
under a paradigm is not
done to falsify the theory, but to fill in and develop the knowledge that the paradigm provides a framework for. The
reasoning involved in developing or replacing a paradigm is not simply
deductive, and there is probably no
adequate single characterization of
how it proceeds. This does not mean that it is irrational or not worth
studying, but that there is no simple universal characterization of good
scientific reasoning. This view of science, or one like it, is widely held by
philosophers now. It has been suggested that philosophy too is governed by
paradigms.
PHILOSOPHY REASONING –
THE ADVERSARY PARADIGM
I am going to criticize a paradigm or part of
a paradigm in philosophy. It is the view that applies the now-rejected view
of value-free reasoning in science to reasoning in philosophy. On this view all
philosophic reasoning is, or ought to be, deductive. General claims are made
and the job of philosophic research is to find counterexamples to the claims.
And most important, THE ADVERSARY METHOD the philosophic enterprise is seen as
an unimpassioned debate between adversaries who try to defend their own views
against counterexamples and produce
counterexamples to opposing views. The
reasoning used to discover the claims, and the way the claims relate to other
beliefs and systems of ideas are not considered relevant to philosophic
reasoning if they are not deductive. I will call this the Adversary Paradigm.
Under the Adversary Paradigm, it is assumed that the only, or at any rate, the best, way of
evaluating work in philosophy is to subject it to the
strongest or most extreme opposition. And it is
assumed that the best way of presenting work in philosophy is to address it to
an imagined opponent and muster all the
evidence one can to support it. The justification for this method is that a
position ought to be defended from, and subjected to, the criticism of the strongest opposition; that this method is
the only way to get the best of both sides; that a thesis
which survives this method of evaluation is more likely
to be correct than one that has not; and that a thesis subjected to the
Adversary Method will have passed an “objective” test, the most extreme test possible, whereas any weaker criticism
or evaluation will,
by comparison, give an advantage to the claim to be evaluated and therefore not
be as objective as it could be. Of course, it will
be admitted that the Adversary Method does not guarantee that all and only sound philosophical claims will survive, but that is only because even an adversary does not
always think of all the things which ought to be
criticized about a position, and even a
proponent does not always think of all the
possible responses to criticism. However, since
there is no way to determine with certainty what is good and what is bad
philosophy, the Adversary Method is the best there is. If one wants philosophy
to be objective, one should prefer the Adversary Method to other, more
subjective, forms of evaluation which would give preferential treatment to some claims by not
submitting them to extreme adversarial tests. Philosophers who accept the
Adversary Paradigm in philosophy may recognize that scientific reasoning is
different, but think “So much the worse for
science. At least philosophy can be
objective and value free.” Used to suggest that an unfortunate event or
situation is the fault of the person specified and that the speaker does not
feel any great concern about it.
‘if they were daft enough to believe it, so much the worse for
them’
I am going to criticize
this paradigm in philosophy. My objection to the Adversary Method is to its
role as a paradigm. If it were merely one procedure among many for philosophers
to employ, there might be nothing worth objecting to except that conditions of hostility are not
likely to elicit the best reasoning.
But when it dominates the methodology and evaluation of
philosophy, it restricts and misrepresents what philosophic reasoning is.
JANICE MOULTON It has been said about science
that criticism of a paradigm, however warranted, will not be successful unless
there is an alternative paradigm
available to replace it.
But the situation in philosophy is different.
It is not that we have to wait for an alternative form of reasoning to be
developed. Nonadversarial reasoning exists both outside and within philosophy
but our present paradigm does not recognize it.
DEFECTS OF THE ADVERSARY
PARADIGM
The defense of the
Adversary Method identified adversary criticism with severe evaluation. If the
evaluation is not adversarial it is assumed it must be weaker and less
effective. I am going to argue that this picture is mistaken. As far back as Plato it was recognized that in order for a debate or discussion to
take place, assumptions must be shared by the parties involved.
A debate is not possible
among people who disagree about everything. Not only must they agree about what
counts as a good argument, what will be acceptable as relevant data, and how to
decide on the winner, but they must share
some premises in order for the debate to
get started. The Adversary Method works best if the
disagreements are isolated ones, about a particular claim or argument. But
claims and arguments about particular things rarely exist in isolation. They are usually part of an interrelated system
of ideas. Under the Adversary Paradigm we find
ourselves trying to disagree with a system of ideas by taking each claim or
argument, one at a time. Premises which might
otherwise be rejected must be accepted, if only temporarily, for the sake of
the argument. We have to fight our opponents
on their terms. And in order to criticize each claim individually, one at a
time, we would have to provisionally accept most of the ideas we
disagree with most of the time. Such a method can distort
the presentation of an opponent’s position, and produce
an artificially slow development of thought.
Moreover, when a whole system of ideas is involved, as it frequently is, a
debate that ends in defeat for one argument, without changing the whole system
of ideas of which that argument was a part, will
only provoke stronger support for other arguments with the same conclusion, or inspire attempts to amend the argument to avoid the objections. Even if the entire
system of ideas is challenged, it is unlikely to be abandoned without an
alternative system to take its place. A
conclusion that is supported by the argument in question may remain undaunted
by the defeat of that argument. In order to
alter a conclusion, it could be more effective to ignore confrontation on the
particular points, not provide counterexamples, however easy THE ADVERSARY METHOD
they may be to find, and instead show how other premises and other data support
an alternative system of ideas. If we are restricted to the Adversary Method we
may have to withhold evaluation for a system of ideas in order to find a common ground for debate.
And the adversarial criticism of some arguments may merely strengthen support
for other ideas in the system, or inspire
makeshift revisions and adjustments.
Moreover, the Adversary Paradigm allows exemptions from criticism of claims in
philosophy that are not well worked out,
that are “programmatic”.
KNOWLEDGE
CLAIMS. A knowledge
claim something that the claimant believes to be true, but is open
to fact-checking, discussion and debate.
Now any thesis in
philosophy worth its salt will be programmatic in that there will be implications which go beyond the thesis itself. But the claims that have become popular in philosophy are
particularly sketchy, and secure their immunity from criticism under the
Adversary Paradigm because their details are not worked out. A programmatic
claim will offer a few examples which fit the claim along with a prediction
that, with some modification (of course), a theory can be developed along these
lines to cover all cases. Counterexamples
cannot refute these claims because objections will be routinely dismissed as
merely things to be considered later,
when all the details are worked out. Programmatic claims have burgeoned in philosophy,
particular in epistemology and philosophy of language. It has become a pattern
for many philosophy papers to spend most of the paper explaining and arguing
against other claims and then to offer a programmatic claim or conjecture of
one’s own as an alternative at the end without any support or elaboration.
(Perhaps this is the beginning of a new
paradigm that is growing out of a shortcoming in the
evaluation procedures of the Adversary
Paradigm.) Some programmatic claims that were once quite popular are now
in disrepute, such as sense-data theories, but not because they were disproved, perhaps more because they
failed to succeed – no one ever worked out the details and/or people gave up
hope of ever doing so. The Adversary Method allows programmatic claims to
remain viable in philosophy, however sketchy or implausible, as long as they
are unrefuted.
Comments
Post a Comment