Bad news isn't wine By Prof Dr Sohail Ansari & probabilistic theories The difference between a saint and a hypocrite is that one lies
for his religion, the other by it. ~ Minna Antrim
Crafting ever new news
·
Bad news does not improve with age; therefore,
journalists are always engaged in crafting new bad news tailored to different
times.
·
Bad news isn't wine. It doesn't improve with
age. Colin Powell
Qur’an is
relevant today
Qur’an is
relevant today, just as it was almost 2 millennia ago. We need to learn to use
it, and make it our friend throughout all stages of life, all circumstances and
all experiences. Including in our student-life.
Here are lessons of
guidance from the Qur’an for students till the end of time:
1. GRATITUDE
The first bridge
connecting humanity with the divine, through His own sacred words is gratitude
and appreciation.
[All] praise is [due] to Allah , Lord of the
worlds (1:2)
The Qur’an begins with
loving appreciation and gratitude to Allah in a verse that is both grammatically timeless and speaker-less. Reminding us that whether anyone thanks Him or
not, all gratitude and appreciation belong to Him.
As students in the
developed world, we’re some of the most collectively ungrateful creatures
walking under the sun. While others would give up an arm just to hold a
textbook in the other, we’re complaining about everything and anything. We need
to remember that foremost, if Allah has given us the time, health, faculties of
thought and opportunity to be in school—any school—it’s our job to show a bit
of appreciation and gratitude. As Allah says,
And [remember] when your Lord proclaimed, ‘If
you are grateful, I will surely increase you [in favor]….(14:7)
The more grateful we
are for our professors, our classmates, the cafeteria food, the boring
mandatory courses—the more Allah will bless our journey in ways we can’t
imagine. Students in Gaza have missile holes where their blackboards are, STOP
COMPLAINING — let’s be grateful for our professors, our education, our degree,
our marks and our experience.
Pro tip: Say “Alḥamdulilāh”
whenever you’re angry or upset at school related issues. Given how frustrating
student life is, making “Alḥamdulilāh” a part of your daily vocabulary means a whole lot of blessings will be coming your way!
Two basic types
probabilistic theories of causation
Potential Counterexamples
Given the basic probability-raising idea, one would expect
putative counterexamples to probabilistic theories of causation to be of two
basic types:
Cases where causes fail to raise the probabilities of their
effects,
Cases where non-causes raise the probabilities of non-effects.
The discussion in the literature has focused primarily on the
first sort of example.
Probability-lowering Causes. Consider the following example, due to
Deborah Rosen (reported in Suppes (1970)).
(i)
A golfer badly slices a golf ball, which heads toward the rough,
but then bounces off a tree and into the cup for a hole-in-one. The golfer's
slice lowered the probability that the ball would wind up in
the cup, yet nonetheless caused this result. One way of avoiding
this problem, suggested in Hitchcock (2004a) is to make causal claims explicitly
contrastive.
Let S represent
the golfer's slicing the ball, H her
hitting a hole-in-one, and B be
the appropriate background context. Now ~S is
actually a disjunction of several alternatives: if the golfer hadn't
sliced the ball, she might have hit the ball cleanly (S′), or missed it
altogether (S″). Rather than saying that the golfer's slicing the ball caused
the hole-in-one, and trying to analyze this claim by comparing P(H | S & B) and P(H | ~S & B), we can make two more
precise contrastive claims. The golfer's slicing the ball, rather than
missing entirely, caused the hole-in-one, as evidenced by the probabilities P(H | S & B) > P(H | S″ & B), but her slicing the
ball rather than hitting it squarely did not cause the ball to go in the hole:
P(H | S & B) < P(H | S′ & B). Hitchcock (1996) and
Schaffer (2005) argue that there are a number of further advantages to taking
causation to have a contrastive structure.
(ii)
Preemption. A different sort of counterexample involves causal preemption.
Suppose that an
assassin puts a weak poison in the king's drink, resulting in a 30% chance of
death. The king drinks the poison and dies. If the assassin had not
poisoned the drink, her associate would have spiked the drink with
an even deadlier elixir (70% chance of death). In the example, the assassin
caused the king to die by poisoning his drink, even though she lowered his
chance of death (from 70% to 30%). Here the cause lowered the
probability of death, because it preempted an even stronger
cause.
One approach to this problem suggested by Dowe (2004) and
Hitchcock (2004b) would be to invoke a distinction
introduced in Section 2.9 above between net and component effects. The
assassin's action affects the king's chances of death in two distinct ways:
First, it introduces
the weak poison into the king's drink.
Second, it prevents
the introduction of a stronger poison.
The net effect is to reduce the king's chance of
death. Nonetheless, we can isolate the first of these effects by holding fixed
the inaction of the associate: given that the associate did not in fact poison the
drink, the assassin's action increased the king's chance of death (from near
zero to .3). We count the assassin's action as a cause of death because it
increased the chance of death along one of the routes connecting the two
events.
(iii)
Probability-raising
non-causes. For a counterexample of the second type, where a
non-cause raises the probability of an outcome,
Suppose that two gunmen shoot at a target. Each
has a certain probability of hitting, and a certain probability of
missing. Assume that none of the probabilities are one or
zero. As a matter of fact, the first gunman hits, and the second gunman
misses. Nonetheless, the second gunman did fire, and by firing, increased
the probability that the target would be hit, which it was. While it is
obviously wrong to say that the second gunman's shot caused the target
to be hit, it would seem that a probabilistic theory of causation is committed
to this consequence. A natural approach to this problem would be to try to combine
the probabilistic theory of causation with a requirement of spatiotemporal
connection between cause and effect. Dowe (2004) proposes an account along
these lines.
it means k saint apne religion k liye jhoot bolta h. jub k hypocrite religion k through jhoot bolta h. like usy use kr k ya phr apne maqsad me kamyaaab hone k liye
ReplyDelete