Affording a cheater a chance
Students of university must be ready to have a series
of engaging dialogues and come up with examples of their own.
By Prof Dr Sohail Ansari Dispute may be used to suppress the light of truth and to
distract people from it. Allah The Almighty Says (what means):
{And indeed do the devils inspire their allies [among men] to dispute with you. And if you were to obey them, indeed, you would be associators [of others with Him].} [Quran 6:121]
{And indeed do the devils inspire their allies [among men] to dispute with you. And if you were to obey them, indeed, you would be associators [of others with Him].} [Quran 6:121]
{They disputed by [using]
falsehood to [attempt to] invalidate thereby the truth. So I seized them, and
how [terrible] was My Penalty.} [Quran 40:5]
{And among them are those
who listen to you, but We have placed over their hearts coverings, lest they
understand it, and in their ears deafness. And if they should see every sign,
they will not believe in it. Even when they come to you arguing with you, those
who disbelieve say, “This is not but legends of the former peoples.”} [Quran 6:25]
Cheater will cheat as long as you believe
he will not
· We afford a cheater an opportunity to cheat
again when we believe that he will not cheat again.
------------------------------------------------------------------
Premise
A premise or premiss[a] is a
statement that an argument claims will induce or justify a conclusion.[3] In
other words: a premise is an assumption that something is true. In logic, an argument requires
a set of (at
least) two declarative sentences (or "propositions") known as the premises or premisses along
with another declarative sentence (or "proposition") known as the conclusion. Aristotle held that any logical argument could be
reduced to two premises and a conclusion.[4]Premises
are sometimes left unstated in which case they are called missing premises, for
example:
Socrates is mortal because
all men are mortal.
It is evident that a tacitly understood claim is that Socrates
is a man. The fully expressed reasoning is thus:
Because all men are mortal
and Socrates is a man, Socrates is mortal.
In this example, the independent clauses preceding the comma (namely, "all men
are mortal" and "Socrates is a man") are the premises, while
"Socrates is mortal" is the conclusion.
The proof of a conclusion depends on both the truth of the premises and the validity of the argument.
Argument
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
In philosophy and logic, an argument is a series of
statements typically used to persuade someone of something or to present
reasons for accepting a conclusion.
There are several kinds of arguments in
logic, the best-known of which are "deductive" and
"inductive." An argument has one or more premises but only one
conclusion. Each premise and the conclusion are truth
bearers or
"truth-candidates", each capable of being either true or false (but
not both). These truth values bear on the terminology used with arguments.
(A truth-bearer is an entity that is said to be
either true or false and nothing else)
Deductive arguments
·
A deductive argument asserts that the truth of the
conclusion is a logical
consequence of the
premises. Based on the premises, the conclusion follows necessarily (with
certainty). For example, given premises that A=B and B=C, then the conclusion
follows necessarily that A=C. Deductive arguments are sometimes referred to as
"truth-preserving" arguments.
·
A deductive argument
is said to be valid or invalid. If one assumes the premises to be true (ignoring
their actual truth values), would the conclusion follow with certainty? If yes,
the argument is valid. Otherwise, it is invalid. In determining validity, the
structure of the argument is essential to the determination, not the actual
truth values. For example, consider the argument that because bats can fly
(premise=true), and all flying creatures are birds (premise=false), therefore
bats are birds (conclusion=false). If we assume the premises are true, the
conclusion follows necessarily, and thus it is a valid argument.
·
If a deductive
argument is valid and its premises are all true, then it is also referred to as
sound. Otherwise, it is unsound, as in the "bats are birds" example.
Inductive arguments
·
An inductive argument,
on the other hand, asserts that the truth of the conclusion is supported to
some degree of probability by the premises. For example, given that the U.S.
military budget is the largest in the world (premise=true), then it is probable
that it will remain so for the next 10 years (conclusion=true). Arguments that
involve predictions are inductive, as the future is uncertain.
·
An inductive argument
is said to be strong or weak. If the premises of an inductive argument are assumed true, is it probable the conclusion is
also true? If so, the argument is strong. Otherwise, it is weak.
·
A strong argument is
said to be cogent if it has all true premises. Otherwise, the argument is
uncogent. The military budget argument example above is a strong, cogent
argument.
Deductive arguments
may be either valid or invalid. If an argument is valid, it is a valid
deduction, and if its premises are true, the conclusion must be true: a valid
argument cannot have true premises and a false conclusion.
An argument is
formally valid if and only if the denial of the conclusion is incompatible with
accepting all the premises.
Some examples:
·
All Greeks are human and all humans
are mortal; therefore, all Greeks are mortal. : Valid
argument; if the premises are true the conclusion must be true.
·
Some Greeks are logicians and some
logicians are tiresome; therefore, some Greeks are tiresome. Invalid
argument: the tiresome logicians might all be Romans (for example).
·
Either we are all doomed or we are
all saved; we are not all saved; therefore, we are all doomed. Valid
argument; the premises entail the conclusion. (Remember that this does not mean
the conclusion has to be true; it is only true if the premises are true, which
they may not be!)
·
Some men are hawkers. Some hawkers
are rich. Therefore, some men are rich. Invalid
argument. This can be easier seen by giving a counter-example with the same
argument form:
·
Some people are herbivores. Some
herbivores are zebras. Therefore, some people are zebras. Invalid
argument, as it is possible that the premises be true and the conclusion false.
In the above second to
last case (Some men are hawkers...), the counter-example follows the same
logical form as the previous argument, (Premise 1: "Some X are Y."
Premise 2: "Some Y are Z." Conclusion:
"Some X are Z.") in order to demonstrate
that whatever hawkers may be, they may or may not be rich, in consideration of
the premises as such.
Defeasible
arguments and argumentation schemes
In modern
argumentation theories, arguments are regarded as defeasible passages from
premises to a conclusion. Defeasibility means that when additional
information (new evidence or contrary arguments) is provided, the premises may
be no longer lead to the conclusion (non-monotonic reasoning). This type of
reasoning is referred to as defeasible
reasoning. For instance we consider the famous Tweedy example:
Tweedy is a bird.
Birds generally fly.
Therefore, Tweedy (probably) flies.
This argument is reasonable and the
premises support the conclusion unless additional information indicating that
the case is an exception comes in. If Tweedy is a penguin, the inference is no
longer justified by the premise. Defeasible arguments are based on
generalizations that hold only in the majority of cases, but are subject to
exceptions and defaults. Argumentation
schemes are stereotypical patterns of inference, combining semantic-ontological
relations with types of reasoning and logical axioms and representing the
abstract structure of the most common types of natural arguments.[10
In informal logic
Argument is an
informal calculus, relating an effort to be performed or sum to be spent, to
possible future gain, either economic or moral. In informal logic, an argument
is a connexion between
a. an individual action
b. through
which a generally accepted good is obtained.
Ex :
1.
a. You
should marry Jane (individual action, individual decision)
b. because
she has the same temper as you. (generally accepted wisdom that marriage is
good in itself, and it is generally accepted that people with the same
character get along well).
2.
a. You
should not smoke (individual action, individual decision)
b. because
smoking is harmful (generally accepted wisdom that health is good).
The argument is
neither a) advice nor b) moral or economical judgement,
but the connection between the two. An argument always uses the connective because.
An argument is not an explanation. It does not connect two events,
cause and effect, which already took place, but a possible individual action
and its beneficial outcome. An argument is not a proof. A proof is
a logical and cognitive concept; an argument is a praxeologic concept. A proof
changes our knowledge; an argument compels us to act
Logical status
Argument does not
belong to logic, because it is connected to a real person, a real event, and a
real effort to be made.
1. If you, John, will buy this stock,
it will become twice as valuable in a year.
2. If you, Mary, study dance, you will
become a famous ballet dancer.
The value of the
argument is connected to the immediate circumstances of the person spoken to.
If, in the first case,(1) John has no money, or knows he has only one year to
live, he will not be interested in buying the stock. If, in the second case (2)
she is too heavy, or too old, she will not be interested in studying and
becoming a dancer. The argument is not logical, but profitable.
Explanations
Main article: Explanation
While arguments
attempt to show that something was, is, will be, or should be the case,
explanations try to show why or how something is or will be. If Fred and
Joe address the issue of whether or not Fred's cat has fleas, Joe may
state: "Fred, your cat has fleas. Observe, the cat is scratching right
now." Joe has made an argument
that the cat has fleas.
However, if Joe asks Fred, "Why is your cat scratching itself?" the
explanation, "...because it has fleas." provides understanding.
Both the above
argument and explanation require knowing the generalities that a) fleas often
cause itching, and b) that one often scratches to relieve itching. The
difference is in the intent: an argument attempts to settle whether or not some claim is
true, and an explanation attempts to provide understanding of the event. Note,
that by subsuming the specific event (of Fred's cat scratching) as an instance
of the general rule that "animals scratch themselves when they have
fleas", Joe will no longer wonder why Fred's cat is scratching itself.
Arguments address problems of belief, explanations address problems of
understanding. Also note that in the argument above, the statement,
"Fred's cat has fleas" is up for debate (i.e. is a claim), but in the
explanation, the statement, "Fred's cat has fleas" is assumed to be
true (unquestioned at this time) and just needs explaining.[17]
Arguments and
explanations largely resemble each other in rhetorical use.
This is the cause of much difficulty in thinking critically about claims. There are several
reasons for this difficulty.
·
People often are not
themselves clear on whether they are arguing for or explaining something.
·
The same types of
words and phrases are used in presenting explanations and arguments.
·
The terms 'explain' or
'explanation,' et cetera are frequently used in arguments.
·
Explanations are often
used within arguments and presented so as to serve as arguments.[18]
·
Likewise,
"...arguments are essential to the process of justifying the validity of
any explanation as there are often multiple explanations for any given
phenomenon."[17]
Explanations and arguments
are often studied in the field of Information
Systems to help
explain user acceptance of knowledge-based systems. Certain argument types may
fit better with personality traits to enhance acceptance by individuals.[19]
Fallacies
and nonarguments
Main article: Formal fallacy
Fallacies are types of
argument or expressions which are held to be of an invalid form or contain
errors in reasoning. There is not as yet any general theory of fallacy or
strong agreement among researchers of their definition or potential for
application but the term is broadly applicable as a label to certain examples
of error, and also variously applied to ambiguous candidates.[20]
In Logic types of
fallacy are firmly described thus: First the premises and the conclusion must
be statements, capable of being true or false. Secondly it must be asserted
that the conclusion follows from the premises. In English the words therefore, so, because and hence typically separate the premises from
the conclusion of an argument, but this is not necessarily so. Thus: Socrates is a man, all men are
mortal therefore Socrates is mortal is
clearly an argument (a valid one at that), because it is clear it is asserted
that Socrates is mortal follows from the preceding statements.
However I was thirsty and
therefore I drank is NOT an
argument, despite its appearance. It is not being claimed that I drank is logically entailed by I was thirsty. The therefore in this sentence indicates for that reason not it
follows that.
Elliptical arguments
Often an argument is
invalid because there is a missing premise—the supply of which would render it
valid. Speakers and writers will often leave out a strictly necessary premise
in their reasonings if it is widely accepted and the writer does not wish to
state the blindingly obvious. Example: All metals expand when heated,
therefore iron will expand when heated. (Missing premise: iron is a
metal). On the other hand, a seemingly valid argument may be found to lack a
premise – a 'hidden assumption' – which if highlighted can show a fault in
reasoning. Example: A witness reasoned: Nobody came out the front door
except the milkman; therefore the murderer must have left by the back door. (Hidden
assumptions- the milkman was not the murderer, and the murderer has left by the
front or back door).
Comments
Post a Comment