The fiction of Capitalist society By Prof Dr Sohail Ansari
Ibn ‘Ashur (1879-1973) in his Treatise on The Maqasid al-Syariah affirms that
one of the objectives of the Syariah concerning all kinds of economic wealth
can be summarised under five headings, one of which is rawaj al-amwal or the fair
circulation of wealth in the hands of as many people as possible without
causing any harm to those who have acquired it lawfully.
True Non-capitalist society is a myth
· Society can’t be
anti-capitalist as long as it likes the things only unequal distribution of
money can buy
Quote:
Good, better, best. Never let it rest. 'Til
your good is better and your better is best. St. Jerome
THE
CONTEXT OF DESIGN
Before examining types of research designs it is important to be
clear about the
role and purpose of research design. We need to understand what research design is and
what it is not. We need to know where design is into the whole research process
from framing a
question to analysing and reporting data.
Description and
explanation
Social researchers ask two fundamental types of
research questions:
1 What is going on (descriptive research)?
2 Why is it going on (explanatory research)?
Descriptive research: Although some people dismiss
descriptive research as `mere description', good description is fundamental to the research
enterprise and it has added immeasurably to our knowledge of the shape and
nature of our society. Descriptive research encompasses much government sponsored
research
including the population
census, the
collection of a wide range of social indicators and economic information such as household expenditure patterns, time use
studies, employment
and crime statistics and the like. Descriptions can be concrete or abstract. A relatively concrete
description might describe the ethnic mix of a community, the changing age of a population or the gender
mix of a workplace. Alternatively the description might ask more abstract questions such as `Is the level of social inequality increasing or declining?', `How
secular is society?' or `How much poverty is there in this community?'
Accurate descriptions of the level of unemployment or poverty have historically
played a key role in social policy reforms (Marsh, 1982). By demonstrating the
existence of social problems, competent description can challenge accepted
assumptions about the way things are and can provoke action. Good description provokes the `why' questions of
explanatory research. If we detect greater social polarization over the last 20
years (i.e. the rich are getting richer and the poor are getting poorer) we are
forced to ask `Why is this happening?' But before asking `why?' we must be sure about the fact and
dimensions of the phenomenon of increasing polarization. It is all very well to
develop elaborate theories as to why society might be more polarized now than
in the recent past, but if the basic premise is wrong (i.e. society is not
becoming more polarized) then attempts to explain a non-existent phenomenon are silly. Of course description
can degenerate
to mindless fact gathering or what C.W. Mills (1959) called `abstracted empiricism'. There are plenty of
examples of unfocused surveys and case studies that report trivial information
and fail to provoke any `why' questions or provide any basis for
generalization. However, this is a function of inconsequential descriptions rather than an indictment of descriptive research
itself.
Explanatory research: Explanatory research focuses on why
questions. For example, it is one thing to describe the crime rate in a country, to examine trends
over time or to compare the rates in different countries. It is quite a
different thing to develop explanations about why the crime rate is as high as it is, why some
types of crime are increasing or why the rate is higher in some countries than
in others. The way in which researchers develop research designs is fundamentally affected
by whether the research question is descriptive or explanatory. It affects what
information is collected. For example, if we want to explain why some people
are more
likely to
be apprehended and convicted of crimes we need to have hunches about why this is so. We may
have many possibly incompatible hunches and will need to collect information
that enables us to see which hunches work best empirically. Answering the `why'
questions involves developing causal explanations. Causal explanations argue that phenomenon Y
(e.g. income level) is affected by factor X (e.g. gender). Some causal explanations will be simple while
others will be more complex. For example, we might argue that there is a direct
effect of gender on income (i.e. simple gender discrimination). We might argue
for a causal chain, such as that gender affects choice of training which in
turn affects
‘WHAT IS RESEARCH DESIGN?’ occupational options, which are linked to opportunities for
promotion, which in turn affect income level. Or we could posit a more complex model
involving a number of interrelated causal chains.
Prediction, correlation and causation: People often confuse
correlation with causation. Simply because one event follows another, or two
factors co-vary, does not mean that one
causes the other. The link between two events may be coincidental rather than
causal. There is a correlation between the number of re engines and the amount
of damage caused by the (the more re engines the more damage). Is it therefore
reasonable to conclude that the number of re engines causes the amount of
damage? Clearly the number of re engines and the amount of damage will both be
due to some third factor such as the
seriousness of the ®re engines. Similarly, as the divorce rate changed over the twentieth
century the crime
rate increased a few years later. But this does not mean that divorce causes
crime. Rather than divorce causing crime, divorce and crime rates might both be
due to other social processes such as secularization, greater individualism or
poverty. Income level Gender a) Direct causal relationship Gender Field of
training Occupation Promotion opportunities Income level b) Indirect causal
relationship: a causal chain c) A more complex causal model of direct and
indirect causal links Gender Child-care responsibility Occupation Part time or
full time work Income level Field of training.
Three types of causal relationships
Students
at fee paying private schools typically perform better in their annual year of
schooling than those at government funded schools. But this need not be because
private schools produce better performance. It may be that attending a private
school and better annual-year performance are both the outcome of some other
cause. Confusing
causation with correlation also confuses prediction with causation and prediction
with explanation. Where two events or characteristics are correlated we can
predict one from the other. Knowing the type of school attended improves our capacity to
predict academic achievement. But this does not mean that the school type affects academic
achievement. Predicting performance on the basis of school type does not tell us why private school
students do better. Good prediction does not depend on causal relationships.
Nor does the ability to predict accurately demonstrate anything about
causality. Recognizing that causation is more than correlation highlights a problem.
While we can observe
correlation we cannot observe cause. We have to infer cause. These inferences
however are `necessarily
fallible .
. . [they] are only indirectly linked to observables' (Cook and Campbell, 1979:
10). Because our inferences are fallible we must minimize the chances of
incorrectly saying that a relationship is causal when in fact it is not. One of
the fundamental purposes of research design in explanatory research is to avoid invalid
inferences. Deterministic
and probabilistic concepts of causation There are two ways of thinking about
causes: deterministically and probabilistically. The smoker who denies that tobacco causes
cancer because
he smokes heavily but has not contracted cancer illustrates deterministic
causation. Probabilistic
causation
is illustrated by health authorities who point to the increased chances of
cancer among smokers. Deterministic causation is where variable X is said to cause Y if, and
only if, X invariably produces Y. That is, when X is present then Y will
`necessarily, inevitably
and infallibly' occur (Cook and Campbell, 1979: 14). This approach seeks to
establish causal laws such as: whenever water is heated to 100 ¾C it always boils. In
reality laws are never this simple. They will always specify particular conditions under
which that law
operates. Indeed a great deal of scientific investigation involves specifying
the conditions under which particular laws operate. Thus, we might say that at sea level heating pure
water to
100 ¾C will always cause water to boil. Alternatively, the law might be stated
in the form of `other things being equal' then X will always produce Y. A deterministic version of the relationship
between race
and income level would say that other things being equal (age, education,
personality, experience etc.) then a white person will always earn a higher
income than a black person. That is, race (X) causes income level (Y).
Stated like this the notion of deterministic
causation in the social sciences sounds odd. It is hard to conceive of a characteristic or
event that will invariably result in a given outcome even if a fairly tight set
of conditions is specified. The complexity of human social behaviour and the
subjective, meaningful and voluntaristic components of human behaviour mean that it will never be
possible to arrive at causal statements of the type `If X, and A and B, then Y
will always follow.' Most causal thinking in the social sciences is probabilistic rather than
deterministic (Suppes, 1970). That is, we work at the level that a given factor
increases (or decreases) the probability of a particular outcome, for example: being female increases the
probability
of working part time; race affects the probability of having a high status job. We can improve
probabilistic explanations by specifying conditions under which X is less likely and more likely to
affect Y. But we will never achieve complete or deterministic explanations. Human behaviour is both willed
and caused:
there is a double-sided
character
to human social behaviour. People construct their social world and there are
creative aspects to human action but this freedom and agency will always be constrained by the
structures
within which people live. Because behaviour is not simply determined we cannot
achieve deterministic explanations. However, because behaviour is constrained
we can achieve
probabilistic
explanations. We can say that a given factor will increase the likelihood of a given outcome but
there will never be certainty about outcomes. Despite the probabilistic nature of causal
statements in the social sciences, much popular, ideological and political
discourse translates
these into
deterministic statements. Findings about the causal effects of class, gender or
ethnicity, for example, are often read as if these factors invariably and completely produce
particular outcomes. One could be forgiven for thinking that social science has demonstrated that gender completely and invariably determines
position in society, roles in families, values and ways of relating to other
people.
Comments
Post a Comment